Beyond the Polis: Aristotle’s Beast
Keywords:
Ancient Philosophy, Politic Philosophy, Aristotle, Beast, ExclusionAbstract
In Aristotelian political philosophy, the biological definition of man as a “political animal” functions as the premise upon which the polis can be created. According to Aristotle, man is an animal characterized by rational and communicative abilities that drive him to build communities in pursuit of the “good life.” This definition of human nature presupposes the creation of the polis as the only space where man can fully develop his virtues and live a full and happy life. However, Aristotle’s conception of the polis, only grants political participation within it to individuals that fit this description. This restriction begets the question of who remains beyond the margins of the polis? Beyond the boundaries of this political space remain all those who make life possible in the polis: women, workers, and slaves. Further yet, beyond all economic and social networks, lies the concept that will be the purpose of this article, the “beast,” a human characterized by a lack of political disposition, both in developed instances (like the polis) and the more primitive ones (like a tribe or the home). Following Aristotle’s logic, bestial men are not useful members of the community because they do not fulfill the role of the political animal, as their actions are not guided by the pursuit of the common good. We will argue that as a result, the beast suffers a triple exclusion: political, because he is denied citizenship; social, since he is barred from participating in the community that supports the polis economically; and, biologically for he is excluded from the conceptual group of human.
References
Aristóteles. (1994). Metafísica (Trad. T. Calvo Martínez). Madrid: Editorial Gredos.
Aristóteles. (1995). The Complete Works of Aristotle . Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press.
Aristóteles. (2005). Política . Madrid: Centro de Estudios Políticos y Constitucionales.
Aristóteles. (2014). Ética a Nicómaco (Trad. M. Araujo & J. Marías). Madrid: Centro de Estudios Políticos y Constitucionales.
Bonitz, H. (1955). Index Aristotelicus . Graz: Akademische Druck- U. Verlagsanstalt.
Depew, D. J. (1995). Humans and Other Political Animals in Aristotle’s History of Animals. Phronesis , 40 (2), pp. 156–181.
Frank, J. (2004). Citizens, Slaves and Foreigners: Aristotle on Human Nature. The American Political Science Review , 98 (1), pp. 91–104.
Freeland, C. (Ed.). (1998). Feminist Interpretations of Aristotle . Pennsylvania: Penn State University Press.
Haworth, A. (2012). Understanding Political Philosophers . London: Routledge.
Homero. (2003). La Ilíada (Trad. L. Segalá). San Juan: Editorial de la Universidad de Puerto Rico.
Johnson, C. (1984). Who is Aristotles Citizen? Phronesis , 29 (1), 73–90.
Kullman, W. (1991). Man as a Political Animal in Aristotle. In D. Keyt & F. Miller Jr. (Eds.), A Companion to Aristotle’s Politics (pp. 94–117). Cambridge: Blackwell.
Mumford, L. (1989). The City in History . New York: Harcourt Inc.
Ober, J. (2001). Political Dissent in Democratic Athens:Intellectual Critics of Popular Rule. Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press.
Preus, A. (1986). Aristotle on healthy and sick souls. The Monist , 69 (3), pp. 416–433.
Preus, A. (2007). Historical Dictionary of Ancient Greek Philosophy . Maryland: The Scarecrow Press, Inc.
Reeve, C. (2009). The Naturalness of the Polis in Aristotle. In G. Anagnostopoulos (Ed.), A Companion to Aristotle (pp. 512–525). Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell Publishing.
Schofield, M. (1999). Saving the City: Philosopher Kings and Other Classical Paradigms. New York: Routledge.
Shields, C. (2009). The Aristotelian Psuche. In G. Anagnostopoulos (Ed.), A Companion to Aristotle (pp. 292–309). Oxford: Blackwell Publishing.
Yack, B. (1993). The Problems of a Political Animal: Community, Justice, and Conflict in Aristotelian Political Thought. California: University of California Press.